La filosofía de la química en la filosofía de la ciencia contemporánea
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.48160/18517072re21.453Palabras clave:
filosofía de la química, reduccionismo, modelos y explicaciones en química, educación en químicaResumen
Sobre la base del supuesto reduccionista según el cual la química puede ser reducida a la física fundamental, ella suele ser considerada una disciplina meramente fenomenológica y, por tanto, una ciencia de un prestigio inferior al de la física. Tal supuesto ha retrasado fuertemente el surgimiento de la filosofía de la química como subdisciplina de la filosofía de la ciencia. Afortunadamente, esa situación ha comenzado a modificarse durante los últimos años: la filosofía de la química se ha convertido en un campo de rápido crecimiento. En el presente artículo se revisan las principales líneas de investigación en la filosofía de la química contemporánea y los beneficios potenciales que puede obtener la educación en química a partir de los trabajos generados por los filósofos de esta disciplina.
Citas
Benfey, T. (2002), “Reflections on the Philosophy of Chemistry and a rallying call for our discipline”, Foundations of Chemistry 2, pp. 195-205.
Bent, H. A. (1984), “Should Orbitals Be X-Rated in Beginning Chemistry Courses?”, Journal of Chemical Education 61, 5, pp. 421-423.
Bunge, M. (1982), “Is Chemistry a Branch of Physics?”, Zeitschrift fur allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 13, pp. 209-223.
Christie, J. y Christie, M. (2003), “Chemical Laws and Theories: A Response to Vihalemm”, Foundations of Chemistry, 5, pp. 165-174.
Crasnow, S. (2000), “How Natural Can Ontology Be?”, Philosophy of Science 67, pp. 114-132.
Dirac, P. A. M. (1929), “Quantum Mechanics of Many-Electron Systems”, Proceedings of the Royal Society, A338, pp. 714-733.
Erduran, S. (2001), “Philosophy of Chemistry: An Emerging Field with Implications for Chemistry Education”, Science & Education 10, pp, 581-593.
Gabel, D. (1999), “Improving Teaching and Learning through Chemistry Education Research: A Look to the Future”, Journal of Chemical Education 76, pp. 548-554.
Gallup, G. A. (1988), “The Lewis Electron-Pair Model, Spectroscopy, and the Role of the Orbital Picture in Describing the Electronic Structure of Molecules”, Journal of Chemical Education 65, pp. 671-674.
Hettema, H. y Kuipers, T. A. (1988), “The Periodic Table –Its Formalization, Status, and Relation to Atomic Theory”, Erkenntnis 28, pp. 387-408.
Hettema, H. y Kuipers, T. A. (2000), “The Formalization of the Periodic Table”, en Structuralist Knowledge Representation: Paradigmatic Examples, Poznan Studies 75, Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp. 285-305.
Humphreys, C. J. (1999), “Electrons See in Orbit”, Nature 401, 2 de septiembre, pp. 21-22.
Jacoby, M. (1999). “Picture-Perfect Orbitals”, Chemical & Engineering News 77, 6 de septiembre, p. 8.
Jenkins, Z. (2002), “Do You Need to Believe in Orbitals to Use Them?: Realism and the Autonomy of Chemistry”, Philosophy of Science Association 18th Biennial Mtg-PSA 2002.
Johnstone, A. (2000), “Teaching of Chemistry – Logical or Psychological?”, Chemistry Education: Research and Practice in Europe 1, pp. 9-15.
Justi, R. y Gilbert, J. (1999), “A Cause of Ahistorical Science Teaching: Use of Hybrid Models”, Science Education 83, 2, pp. 163-177.
Kemeny, J. G. y Oppenheim, P. (1956), “On Reduction”, Philosophical Studies 7, pp. 6-19.
Lombardi, O. y Labarca, M. (2005a). “The Ontological Autonomy of the Chemical World”, Foundations of Chemistry, a aparecer en número a designar.
Lombardi, O. y Labarca, M. (2005b), “The philosophy of chemistry as a new resource for chemistry education”, enviado a Journal of Chemical Education.
Luisi, P. L. (2002), “Emergence in Chemistry: Chemistry as the Embodiment of Emergence”, Foundations of Chemistry 4, pp. 183-200.
Melrose, M. P. y Scerri, E. R. (1996), “Why the 4s Orbital Is Occupied Before the 3d”, Journal of Chemical Education 73, pp. 498-503.
Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science, Harcourt, Nueva York, Brace & World.
Niaz, M. y Rodríguez, M. A. (2001), “Do We Have to Introduce History and Philosophy of Science or Is It Already ‘Inside’ Chemistry?”, Chemistry Education: Research and Practice in Europe 2, pp. 159-164.
Ogilvie, J. F. (1990), “The Nature of the Chemical Bond-1990: There Are No Such Things as Orbitals!”, Journal of Chemical Education 67, pp. 280-289.
Paneth, F. (2003), “The Epistemological Status of the Chemical Concept of Element”, Foundations of Chemistry 5, pp. 113-145. Reimpreso del British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 1962, Parte I, 13, pp. 1-14, y Parte II, 13, pp. 144-160.
Pascual, J. I., Gómez-Herrero, J., Rogero, C., Baró, A. M., Sánchez-Portal, D., Artacho, E., Ordejón, P. y Soler, J. M. (2000), “Seeing Molecular Orbitals”, Chemical Physical Letters 321, pp. 78-82.
Pilar, F. (1981), “Damn the Permanganate Volcanoes: Full Principles Ahead!”, Journal of Chemical Education 58, 10, p. 803.
Primas, H. (1983), Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics and Reductionism, Springer, Berlín.
Ramsey, J. (1997), “Molecular Shape, Reduction, Explanation and Approximate Concepts”, Synthese, 111, pp. 233-251.
Richards, G. (1979), “Third Age of Quantum Chemistry”, Nature 278, 5 de abril, p. 507.
Sanderson, R. T. (1986), “Is the Theoretical Emperor Really Wearing Any Clothes?”, Journal of Chemical Education 63, pp. 845-846.
Scerri, E. (1989), “Transition Metal Configurations and Limitations of the Orbital Approximation”, Journal of Chemical Education 66, pp. 481-483.
Scerri, E. (1991), “Chemistry, Spectroscopy, and the Question of Reduction”, Journal of Chemical Education 68, pp. 122-126.
Scerri, E. (1994), “Has Chemistry Been at Least Approximately Reduced to Quantum Mechanics”, Philosophy of Science Association 1, pp. 160-170.
Scerri, E. (1997), “Has the Periodic Table been successfully axiomatized?, Erkenntnis 47, pp. 229-243.
Scerri, E. (1998), “How Good is the Quantum Mechanical Explanation of the Periodic System?”, Journal of Chemical Education 75, pp. 1384-1385.
Scerri, E. (2000a), “Philosophy of Chemistry: A New Interdisciplinary Field?”, Journal of Chemical Education 77, pp. 522-525.
Scerri, E. (2000b), “Have Orbitals Really Been Observed?”, Journal of Chemical Education 77, pp. 1492-1494.
Scerri, E. (2000c), “Realism, Reduction and the ‘Intermediate Position’”, en Bhushan, N. y Rosenfeld, S. (eds.), Of Minds and Molecules. New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry, Nueva York, Oxford University Press, pp. 51-72.
Scerri, E. (2001a), “The Recently Claimed Observation of Atomic Orbitals and Some Related Philosophical Issues”, Philosophy of Science 68, pp. S76-S78.
Scerri, E. (2001b), “The New Philosophy of Chemistry and Its Relevance to Chemical Education”, Chemistry Education: Research and Practice in Europe 2, pp- 165-170.
Scerri, E. (2003a), “Philosophy of Chemistry”, Chemistry International, mayo-junio, pp. 7-9.
Scerri, E. (2003b), “Philosophical Confusión in Chemical Education Research”, Journal of Chemical Education 80, pp. 468-474.
Scerri, E. (2004), “Just How Ab Initio is Ab Initio Quantum Chemistry?, Foundations of Chemistry 6, pp. 93-116.
Scerri, E. y McIntyre, L. (1997), “The Case for the Philosophy of Chemistry”, Synthese 111, pp. 213-232.
Simoes, A. (2002), “Dirac’s Claim and the Chemists”, Physics in Perspective 4, pp. 253-266.
Spence, J. C., O’Keefe, M., Zuo, J. M. (2001), “Have Orbitals Really Been Observed?”, Journal of Chemical Education 78, p. 877.
Tomasi, J. (1999), “Towards ‘Chemical Congruence’ of the Models in Theoretical Chemistry”, Hyle 5 (2), pp. 79-115.
Trindle, C. (1984), “The Hierarchy of Models in Chemistry”, Croatica Chemica Acta 57 (6), pp. 1231-1245.
Tsarpalis, G. (1997), “Atomic and Molecular Structure in Chemical Education”, Journal of Chemical Education 74, pp. 922-925.
Vancik, H. (1999), “Opus Magnum: An Outline for the Philosophy of Chemistry”, Foundations of Chemistry 1, pp. 242-256.
Vanquickenborne, L.G., Pierloot, K. y Devoghel, D. (1989), “Electronic Configuration and Orbital Energies: The 3d-4s Problem”, Inorganic Chemistry 28 (10), pp. 1805-1813.
Vemulapalli, G. K. y Byerly, H. (1999), “Remnants of Reductionism”, Foundations of Chemistry 1, pp. 17-41.
Van Brakel, J. (1986), “The Chemistry of Substances and the Philosophy of Mass Term”, Synthese 69, pp. 291-323.
Van Brakel, J. (1997), “Chemistry as the Science of the Transformation of Substances”, Synthese 111, pp. 253-282.
Van Brakel, J. (2000), “The Nature of Chemical Substances”, en Bhushan, N. y Rosenfeld, S. (eds.), Of Minds and Molecules. New Philosophical Perspectives on Chemistry, Nueva York, Oxford University Press, pp.162-184.
Vihalemm, R. (2003), “Are Laws of Nature and Scientific Theories Peculiar in Chemistry? Scrutinizing Mendeleiev’s Discovery”, Foundations of Chemistry 5, pp. 7-22.
Wang, S. G. y Schwarz, W. H. E. (2000), “On Closed-Shell Interactions, Polar Covalences, d Shell Holes, and Direct Images of Orbitals: The Case of Cuprite”, Angewandte Chemie Int. Edition 39, pp. 1757-1762.
Weininger, S. J. (1984), “The Molecular Structure Conundrum: Can Classical Chemistry be Reduced to Quantum Chemistry?”, Journal of Chemical Education, 61: 939-943.
Wooley, R. G. (1978). “Must a Molecule Have a Shape?”, American Chemical Society 100, pp. 1073-1078.
Wooley, R. G. (1985), “The Molecular Structure Conundrum”, Journal of Chemical Education 62, pp. 1082-1084.
Yam, P. (1999), “Seeing the Bonds”, Scientific American 281, noviembre, p. 28.
Zuckerman, J. J. (1986), “The Coming Renaissance of Descriptive Chemistry”, Journal of Chemical Education 63, 10, pp. 829-833.
Zuo, J. M., Kim, M., O’Keefe, M., y Spence, J. C. H. (1999), “Direct observation of d-orbital holes and Cu-Cu bonding in Cu2O”, Nature 401, 2 de septiembre, pp. 49-52.
Zurer, P. (1999), “Chemistry’s Top Five Achievements”, Chemical & Engineering News 77, 29 de noviembre, pp. 38-40.
Descargas
Publicado
Cómo citar
Número
Sección
Licencia
Derechos de autor 2005 Redes. Revista de Estudios Sociales de la Ciencia y la TecnologíaLos documentos aquí publicados se rigen bajos los criterios de licencia Creative Commons Argentina.Atribución - No Comercial - Sin Obra Derivada 2.5 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ar/